Souvenir C: A Severe Tester’s Translation Guide (Excursion 1 Tour II)

.

I will continue to post mementos and, at times, short excerpts following the pace of one “Tour” a week, in sync with some book clubs reading Statistical Inference as Severe Testing: How to Get Beyond the Statistics Wars (SIST or Statinfast 2018, CUP), e.g., Lakens. This puts us at Excursion 2 Tour I, but first, here’s a quick Souvenir (Souvenir C) from Excursion 1 Tour II:

Souvenir C: A Severe Tester’s Translation Guide

Just as in ordinary museum shops, our souvenir literature often probes treasures that you didn’t get to visit at all. Here’s an example of that, and you’ll need it going forward. There’s a confusion about what’s being done when the significance tester considers the set of all of the outcomes leading to a d(x) greater than or equal to 1.96, i.e., {x: d(x) ≥ 1.96}, or just d(x) ≥ 1.96. This is generally viewed as throwing away the particular x, and lumping all these outcomes together. What’s really happening, according to the severe tester, is quite different. What’s actually being signified is that we are interested in the method, not just the particular outcome. Those who embrace the LP make it very plain that data-dependent selections and stopping rules drop out. To get them to drop in, we signal an interest in what the test procedure would have yielded. This is a counterfactual and is altogether essential in expressing the properties of the method, in particular, the probability it would have yielded some nominally significant outcome or other.

When you see Pr(d(X) ≥ d(x0); H0), or Pr(d(X) ≥ d(x0); H1), for any particular alternative of interest, insert:

“the test procedure would have yielded”

just before the d(X). In other words, this expression, with its inequality, is a signal of interest in, and an abbreviation for, the error probabilities associated with a test.

Applying  the  Severity  Translation.  In  Exhibit  (i),  Royall  described a significance test with a Bernoulli(θ) model, testing H0: θ ≤ 0.2 vs. H1: θ >0.2. We blocked an inference from observed difference d(x) = 3.3 to θ = 0.8 as follows. (Recall that x= 0.53 and d(x0) ≃ 3.3.)

We computed Pr(d(X) > 3.3; θ = 0.8) ≃1.

We translate it as Pr(The test would yield d(X) > 3.3; θ = 0.8) ≃1.

We then reason as follows:

Statistical inference: If θ = 0.8, then the method would virtually always give a difference larger than what we observed. Therefore, the data indicate θ < 0.8.

(This follows for rejecting H0 in general.) When we ask: “How often would your test have found such a significant effect even if H0 is approximately true?” we are asking about the properties of the experiment that did happen. The counterfactual “would have” refers to how the procedure would behave in general, not just with these data, but with other possible data sets in the sample space.

Categories: Statistical Inference as Severe Testing | Leave a comment

Post navigation

I welcome constructive comments for 14-21 days. If you wish to have a comment of yours removed during that time, send me an e-mail.

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s

Blog at WordPress.com.