Getting Credit (or blame) for Something You Didn’t Do (BP oil spill, comedy hour)

UnknownThree years ago, many of us were glued to the “spill cam” showing, in real time, the gushing oil from the April 20, 2010 explosion sinking the Deepwater Horizon oil rig in the Gulf of Mexico, killing 11, and spewing oil until July 15. Trials have been taking place this month, as people try to meet the 3 year deadline to sue BP and others. But what happened to the 200 million gallons of oil?  (Is anyone up to date on this?)  Has it vanished or just sunk to the bottom of the sea by dispersants which may have caused hidden destruction of sea life? I don’t know, but given it’s Saturday night around the 3 year anniversary, let’s listen into a reblog of a spill-related variation on the second of two original “overheard at the comedy hour” jokes. 

In effect, it accuses the frequentist error-statistical account of licensing the following (make-believe) argument after the 2010 oil spill:

Oil Exec: We had highly reliable evidence that H: the pressure was at normal levels on April 20, 2010!

Senator: But you conceded that whenever your measuring tool showed dangerous or ambiguous readings, you continually lowered the pressure, and that the stringent “cement bond log” test was entirely skipped.

 Oil Exec:  Granted, we omitted reliable checks on April 20, 2010, but usually we do a better job—I am reporting the average!  You see, we use a randomizer that most of the time directs us to run the gold-standard check on pressure. But, but April  20 just happened to be one of those times we did the nonstringent test; but on average we do ok.

Senator:  But you don’t know that your system would have passed the more stringent test you didn’t perform!

Oil Exec:  That’s the beauty of the the frequentist test!

Even if we grant (for the sake of the joke) that overall, this “test” rarely errs in the report it outputs (pass or fail),  that is irrelevant to appraising the inference from the data on April 20, 2010 (which would have differed had the more stringent test been run). That interpretation violates the severity criterion:  the observed passing result was altogether common if generated from a source where the pressure level was unacceptably high, Therefore it misinterprets the actual data. The question is why anyone would saddle the frequentist with such shenanigans on averages?  … Lest anyone think I am inventing a criticism, here is a familiar statistical instantiation, where the choice for each experiment is given to be .5 (Cox 1958).

Two Measuring Instruments with Different Precisions:

 A single observation X is to be made on a normally distributed random variable with unknown mean m, but the measurement instrument is chosen by a coin flip: with heads we use instrument E’ with a known small variance, say 10-4, while with tails, we use E”, with a known large variance, say 104. The full data indicates whether E’ or E” was performed, and the particular value observed, which we can write as x’ and x”, respectively. (This example comes up in, ton o’bricks).

In applying our test T+ (see November 2011 blog post ) to a null hypothesis, say, µ = 0, the “same” value of X would correspond to a much smaller p-value were it to have come from E’ than if it had come from E”.  Denote the two p-values as p’ and p”, respectively.  However, or so the criticism proceeds, the error statistician would report the average p-value:  .5(p’ + p”).

But this would give a misleading assessment of the precision and corresponding severity with either measurement! Instead you should report the p-value of the result in the experiment actually run (this is Cox’s Weak Conditionality Principle, WCP).

But what could lead the critic to suppose the error statistician must average over experiments not even performed?  Rule #2 for legitimate criticism is to give the position being criticized the most generous construal one can think of.  Perhaps the critic supposes what is actually a distortion of even the most radical behavioristic construal:

  •   If you consider outcomes that could have occurred in hypothetical repetitions of this experiment, you must also consider other experiments you did not run (but could have been run) in reasoning from the data observed (from the test you actually ran), and report some kind of frequentist average!

The severity requirement makes explicit that such a construal is to be rejected—I would have thought it obvious, and not in need of identifying a special principle. Since it wasn’t, I articulated this special notion for interpreting tests and the corresponding severity criterion.

Let me now give a special (the first!) honorary mention to Christian Robert [2] on this point, as raised in Cox and Mayo (2010).  He writes p. 9 http://arxiv.org/abs/1111.5827:

A compelling section is the one about the weak conditionality principle (pp.294- 298), as it objects to the usual statement that a frequency approach breaks this principle. In a mixture experiment about the same parameter θ, inferences made conditional on the experiment “are appropriately drawn in terms of the sampling behaviour in the experiment known to have been performed” (p. 296). This seems hardly objectionable, as stated. And I must confess the sin of stating the opposite as The Bayesian Choice has this remark (Robert (2007), Example 1.3.7, p.18) that the classical confidence interval averages over the experiments. The term experiment validates the above conditioning in that several experiments could be used to measure θ, each with a different p-value. I will not argue with this.

He would want me to mention that he does raise some caveats:

I could, however, [argue] about ‘conditioning is warranted to achieve objective frequentist goals’ (p. 298) in that the choice of the conditioning, among other things, weakens the objectivity of the analysis. In a sense the above pirouette out of the conditioning principle paradox suffers from the same weakness, namely that when two distributions characterise the same data (the mixture and the conditional distributions), there is a choice to be made between “good” and “bad”.

But there is nothing arbitrary about regarding as “good” the only experiment actually run and from which the actual data arose.  The severity criterion only makes explicit what is/should be already obvious. Objectivity, for us, is directed by the goal of making correct and warranted inferences, not freedom from thinking. After all, any time an experiment E is performed, the critic could insist that the decision to perform E is the result of some chance circumstances and with some probability we might have felt differently that day and have run some other test, perhaps a highly imprecise test or a much more precise test or anything in between, and demand that we report whatever average properties they come up with.  The error statistician can only shake her head in wonder that this gambit is at the heart of criticisms of frequentist tests.

Still, we exiled ones can’t be too fussy, and Robert still gets the mention for conceding that we have  a solid leg on which to pirouette.


[1] You can search the blog for connections between this event, the June 2010 conference at the LSE (especially the RMM volume), my introduction to deepwater drilling, and the blog’s “mascot” stock, Diamond offshore, DO, which, incidentally, just had earnings.

[2] There have been around 4-5 others since then, not sure.


Categories: Bayesian/frequentist, Comedy, Statistics

Post navigation

2 thoughts on “Getting Credit (or blame) for Something You Didn’t Do (BP oil spill, comedy hour)

  1. Terms I learned from the 2010 oil spill: blind shear ram, blowout preventer, top kill, junk shot, junk kill, top cap, cement bond log, kill weight, bullheading, corexit, containment booms, mud pump, remote operated vehicles (ROVs), static kill, bottom kill, relief well, annular preventers, vessels of opportunity, elastomeric packing unit.

  2. I found myself just posting a completely different howler in commenting on Normal Deviate just now:
    http://normaldeviate.wordpress.com/2013/04/27/the-perils-of-hypothesis-testing-again/#comments
    Oy!

Blog at WordPress.com.