“The Supernal Powers Withhold Their Hands And Let Me Alone” : C.S. Peirce

C. S. Peirce: 10 Sept, 1839-19 April, 1914

C. S. Peirce: 10 Sept, 1839-19 April, 1914

Memory Lane* in Honor of C.S. Peirce’s Birthday:
(Part 3) of “Peircean Induction and the Error-Correcting Thesis”

Deborah G. Mayo
Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 41(2) 2005: 299-319

(9/10) Peircean Induction and the Error-Correcting Thesis (Part I)

(9/10) (Part 2) Peircean Induction and the Error-Correcting Thesis

8. Random sampling and the uniformity of nature

We are now at the point to address the final move in warranting Peirce’s [self-correcting thesis] SCT. The severity or trustworthiness assessment, on which the error correcting capacity depends, requires an appropriate link (qualitative or quantitative) between the data and the data generating phenomenon, e.g., a reliable calibration of a scale in a qualitative case, or a probabilistic connection between the data and the population in a quantitative case. Establishing such a link, however, is regarded as assuming observed regularities will persist, or making some “uniformity of nature” assumption—the bugbear of attempts to justify induction.

But Peirce contrasts his position with those favored by followers of Mill, and “almost all logicians” of his day, who “commonly teach that the inductive conclusion approximates to the truth because of the uniformity of nature” (2.775). Inductive inference, as Peirce conceives it (i.e., severe testing) does not use the uniformity of nature as a premise. Rather, the justification is sought in the manner of obtaining data. Justifying induction is a matter of showing that there exist methods with good error probabilities. For this it suffices that randomness be met only approximately, that inductive methods check their own assumptions, and that they can often detect and correct departures from randomness.

… It has been objected that the sampling cannot be random in this sense. But this is an idea which flies far away from the plain facts. Thirty throws of a die constitute an approximately random sample of all the throws of that die; and that the randomness should be approximate is all that is required. (1.94)

Peirce backs up his defense with robustness arguments. For example, in an (attempted) Binomial induction, Peirce asks, “what will be the effect upon inductive inference of an imperfection in the strictly random character of the sampling” (2.728). What if, for example, a certain proportion of the population had twice the probability of being selected? He shows that “an imperfection of that kind in the random character of the sampling will only weaken the inductive conclusion, and render the concluded ratio less determinate, but will not necessarily destroy the force of the argument completely” (2.728). This is particularly so if the sample mean is near 0 or 1. In other words, violating experimental assumptions may be shown to weaken the trustworthiness or severity of the proceeding, but this may only mean we learn a little less.

Yet a further safeguard is at hand:

Nor must we lose sight of the constant tendency of the inductive process to correct itself. This is of its essence. This is the marvel of it. …even though doubts may be entertained whether one selection of instances is a random one, yet a different selection, made by a different method, will be likely to vary from the normal in a different way, and if the ratios derived from such different selections are nearly equal, they may be presumed to be near the truth. (2.729)

Here, the marvel is an inductive method’s ability to correct the attempt at random sampling. Still, Peirce cautions, we should not depend so much on the self-correcting virtue that we relax our efforts to get a random and independent sample. But if our effort is not successful, and neither is our method robust, we will probably discover it. “This consideration makes it extremely advantageous in all ampliative reasoning to fortify one method of investigation by another” (ibid.).

“The Supernal Powers Withhold Their Hands And Let Me Alone”

Peirce turns the tables on those skeptical about satisfying random sampling—or, more generally, satisfying the assumptions of a statistical model. He declares himself “willing to concede, in order to concede as much as possible, that when a man draws instances at random, all that he knows is that he tried to follow a certain precept” (2.749). There might be a “mysterious and malign connection between the mind and the universe” that deliberately thwarts such efforts. He considers betting on the game of rouge et noire: “could some devil look at each card before it was turned, and then influence me mentally” to bet or not, the ratio of successful bets might differ greatly from 0.5. But, as Peirce is quick to point out, this would equally vitiate deductive inferences about the expected ratio of successful bets.

Consider our informal example of weighing with calibrated scales. If I check the properties of the scales against known, standard weights, then I can check if my scales are working in a particular case. Were the scales infected by systematic error, I would discover this by finding systematic mismatches with the known weights; I could then subtract it out in measurements. That scales have given properties where I know the object’s weight indicates they have the same properties when the weights are unknown, lest I be forced to assume that my knowledge or ignorance somehow influences the properties of the scale. More generally, Peirce’s insightful argument goes, the experimental procedure thus confirmed where the measured property is known must work as well when it is unknown unless a mysterious and malign demon deliberately thwarts my efforts.

Peirce therefore grants that the validity of induction is based on assuming “that the supernal powers withhold their hands and let me alone, and that no mysterious uniformity … interferes with the action of chance” (ibid.). But this is very different from the uniformity of nature assumption.

…the negative fact supposed by me [no mysterious force interferes with the action of chance] is merely the denial of any major premise from which the falsity of the inductive conclusion could be deduced. Actually so long as the influence of this mysterious source not be overwhelming, the wonderful self-correcting nature of the ampliative inference would enable us, even so, to detect and make allowance for them. (2.749)

Not only do we not need the uniformity of nature assumption, Peirce declares “That there is a general tendency toward uniformity in nature is not merely an unfounded, it is an absolutely absurd, idea in any other sense than that man is adapted to his surroundings” (2.750). In other words, it is not nature that is uniform, it is we who are able to find patterns enough to serve our needs and interests. But the validity of inductive inference does not depend on this.

9. Conclusion

For Peirce, “the true guarantee of the validity of induction” is that it is a method of reaching conclusions which corrects itself; inductive methods—understood as methods of severe testing—are justified to the extent that they are error-correcting methods (SCT). I have argued that the well-known skepticism as regards Peirce’s SCT is based on erroneous views concerning the nature of inductive testing as well as what is required for a method to be self-correcting. By revisiting these two theses, justifying the SCT boils down to showing that severe testing methods exist and that they enable reliable means for learning from error.

An inductive inference to hypothesis H is warranted to the extent that H passes a severe test, that is, one which, with high probability, would have detected a specific flaw or departure from what H asserts, and yet it did not. Deliberately making use of known flaws and fallacies in reasoning with limited and uncertain data, tests may be constructed that are highly trustworthy probes in detecting and discriminating errors in particular cases. Modern statistical methods (e.g., statistical significance tests) based on controlling a test’s error probabilities provide tools which, when properly interpreted, afford severe tests. While on the one hand, contemporary statistical methods increase the mathematical rigor and generality of Peirce’s SCT, on the other, Peirce provides something current statistical methodology lacks: an account of inductive inference and a philosophy of experiment that links the justification for statistical tests to a more general rationale for scientific induction. Combining the mathematical contributions of modern statistics with the inductive philosophy of Peirce sets the stage for developing an adequate solution to the age-old problem of induction. To carry out this project fully is a topic for future work.**

[You can find a pdf version of this paper here.]

REFERENCES and Notes (see part 1)

*This is reblogged from 1 year ago. If there’s a single philosopher I’d say will reward your careful rereading, it’s Peirce. Maybe a glimmer of the idea of inductive-statistical inference as severe testing will shine through…

**That was 2005; I think (hope) I’ve made headway since then.

Categories: C.S. Peirce, Error Statistics, phil/history of stat | 11 Comments

Post navigation

11 thoughts on ““The Supernal Powers Withhold Their Hands And Let Me Alone” : C.S. Peirce

  1. Does anyone ever use the word “supernal” for supernatural any more? I doubt it. But I think the way Peirce turns the tables on the skeptic is brilliant:
    “Peirce therefore grants that the validity of induction is based on assuming ‘that the supernal powers withhold their hands and let me alone, and that no mysterious uniformity … interferes with the action of chance’ (ibid.). But this is very different from the uniformity of nature assumption.”

    Philosophers, by and large, still think that scientific induction is based on the uniformity of nature; not much different from Mill (but correct me if you know counterexamples). This leads to their skepticism, and then multiple ways to live with it.

    By the way, I came across a wonderfully critical review by Peirce of K. Pearson’s “The Grammar of Science” a few months ago. I should try to post it some time, if possible.

  2. Good day, Dr. Mayo. When some analysts start inductive process they asume uniformity of nature by estimating mean as the arithmetic average of dataset, plus estimating variance from a function of U. Then they use U and variance as parameters of a human made parametric model -like Gaussian curves- to build their final model, which produce a different set of frequences for same events. Does this imply that they use a double premise to fill initial ignorance about data frequencies -which only require one premise-?
    In that case, is this a human mistake or a “supernal” event that distorts the induction process?
    Emilio Chaves, Colombia

    • I don’t understand what you mean by using a double premise.

      • I wrote “Does this imply that they use a double premise to fill initial ignorance about data frequencies -which only require one premise-?”
        It is not clear, indeed. I meant that if we supose equal frequences for each dataset value, then the distribution that relates frequences to data is asumed and analysis may be made only from that premise using only data. If we asume a priori a parametric function like Normal curves, then it follows a distribution structure different from the previous one, and neither mean value, neither variance can be obtained from itself. That is the reason -in my opinion- why parametric analysts appeal to the first structural premise of equal frequences to estimate media and dispersion parameters. Once done, they forget it and explains distribution only as a particular parametric case.
        Equal frequences assumption is also called “Laplace Criterion”. It assumes 1/N frequence for each measured value, but this also implies that each value is considered as a media Ui of a tiny sector of width 1/N that surrounds each Ui.
        Thanks, emilio

  3. Christian Hennig

    When I click on your “Part 1” and “Part 2”-links, WordPress is asking me for a login and passwort, which I don’t have…

  4. > In other words, it is not nature that is uniform, it is we who are able to find patterns enough to serve our needs and interests.”

    That we are here, implies there is some uniformity of nature – enough to find patterns to serve our needs and interests.

    My take on some of Peirce’s writings here is that inference has a limited (unknown) shelf life (random samples/comparisons need to be continually redone over time). Also, I think your take is mainly on his quantitative induction – that with randomization induction is deductive or a mathematical fact. (But I never quite grasped his sense of qualitative deduction when randomization is absent.)

    Peirce is worth re-re-re-reading, but folks seem to have a hard time knowing where and how much and especially where to begin. And as you know there are many versions of his manuscripts, the final one seldom clear and many still not that available. So when one claims to know his (final) view on something they are in Peirce’s words standing on a place in a bog that is about to give way.

    • Keith:
      I discuss the connection between qualitative and quantitative–it’s just a matter of degree. consider “crude induction”, his “pooh pooh” argument. Essentially an argument from ignorance. Lacking evidence of the falsity of H, adopt H (provisionally). It will error-correct eventually–with a bang.
      “That we are here, implies there is some uniformity of nature – enough to find patterns to serve our needs and interests.”
      It’s rather, as he shows mathematically, that there’s no kind of non-uniformity that would not be capable of being reined in….

      I am not one of the people who thinks Peirce’s views changed –at least wrt the only area I really know his work well (phil sci-induction-explanation). If there are changes between realism and realisticism or whatever (and I’ve heard Peirce scholars on this) it scarcely matters. the important stuff is, not so much the same, but it gives a unified picture with the usual growth in a scholar’s thinking over time.
      If I had you in a seminar some time I’d have a much better opportunity to explain.

  5. Little story on a Peirce experience: NSA: NOTHING I’M WRITING IS CLASSIFIED .
    At one point, around 2002, one of the national security associations in the U.S. contacted me about a research project they were starting on Peirce in relation to homeland security.
    Why Peirce? the story seemed to be that the Russians were using Peirce’s logic. (It turns out, by the way, that he had already invented systems found out about only recently.) Someone said the Russians had wanted to study Popper but on account of his Open Society could not.

    So did I get involved? yes, but I’d better save the rest of the story…

I welcome constructive comments that are of relevance to the post and the discussion, and discourage detours into irrelevant topics, however interesting, or unconstructive declarations that "you (or they) are just all wrong". If you want to correct or remove a comment, send me an e-mail. If readers have already replied to the comment, you may be asked to replace it to retain comprehension.

Blog at WordPress.com.